Advertisement
If you have a new account but are having problems posting or verifying your account, please email us on hello@boards.ie for help. Thanks :)
Hello all! Please ensure that you are posting a new thread or question in the appropriate forum. The Feedback forum is overwhelmed with questions that are having to be moved elsewhere. If you need help to verify your account contact hello@boards.ie

Global evidence of extreme intuitive moral prejudice against atheists

Options
2»

Comments

  • Closed Accounts Posts: 13,992 ✭✭✭✭recedite


    smacl wrote: »
    One common prejudice of most large groups is greater suspicion of those who are not part of that group, and I suspect that is what we're seeing in this study.
    Maybe to some extent, but the more interesting phenomenon is when the minority group shares the "prejudice" against itself, as in...
    Scofflaw wrote: »
    Apparently, not only religious people, but also atheists, are likely to intuitively associate atheism with moral transgressions...


  • Registered Users Posts: 26,511 ✭✭✭✭Peregrinus


    That wouldn't be uncommon, rec. Societal prejudice against minority groups or outgroups can be pretty powerful, and can affect individuals even from within the group concerned. Gay people can absorb negative attitudes towards homosexuality, women can internalise negative attitudes to women, etc, etc.

    I'm not saying that's what has happened here. As already noted, the study doesn't explore the source of the negative perceptions that it claims to detect. But the fact that atheists themselves seem to share this negative stereotype is certainly consistent with the idea that it is socially inculcated.

    (Of course, it's also consistent with the idea that the negative stereotype is actually objectively correct. But I'll let someone else pull the pin on that hand grenade. ;))


  • Moderators, Society & Culture Moderators Posts: 15,754 Mod ✭✭✭✭smacl


    recedite wrote: »
    Maybe to some extent, but the more interesting phenomenon is when the minority group shares the "prejudice" against itself, as in...

    It is an odd one alright, although the respondents didn't self label as atheists, they merely indicated they didn't believe in God. As such they could still be part of a religious culture that bears prejudice towards atheists and self identify as religious. Purely speculation, but in much the same way as gays in a homophobic environment may exhibit homophobia, atheists in a religious environment might well exhibit anti-atheist prejudices as part of their struggle with a lack of faith.

    Edit: @Peregrinus, beat me to it!


  • Closed Accounts Posts: 13,992 ✭✭✭✭recedite


    Peregrinus wrote: »
    But I'll let someone else pull the pin on that hand grenade.
    Well, I suggested earlier that the perception could be partly true, but in real life balanced by other factors that are less easily perceived.
    Therefore behavioral realities would not necessarily conform to the preconceptions.


  • Registered Users Posts: 23,899 ✭✭✭✭One eyed Jack


    Scofflaw wrote: »
    The point of using the conjunction fallacy, though, is that it shows when a "believable narrative" beats rationality. So what the study shows is that without thinking about it people find the narrative of an atheist committing immoral actions more believable than that of a believer doing so. It doesn't tell us, or rely on, why that's so.

    That might be an uncomfortable observation for us atheists, and it's also wrong as a heuristic, but it's an observation. You do sound to me somewhat as if you'd prefer the observation to be different.

    cordially,
    Scofflaw


    I don't know that I'd agree that it shows us that without thinking about it people were more likely to believe an atheist more capable of immoral acts than a theist. That's the thing I find very unusual in their methodology for testing unconscious bias and prejudice against atheists. I think in order to truly test bias and prejudice against atheists they would have had to ask questions more along the lines of presenting a moral dilema scenario and asking what would either an atheist or a theist be more likely to do in that scenario, rather than presenting a scenario where a person has already committed the immoral action and then asking participants whether the person is more likely to be atheist or theist.

    With regard to why people may believe a person who carries out an immoral action is more likely to be an atheist (this is what I mean by backwards rationalisation after the fact, and why I'm suggesting that the method I outlined above would be better), I don't know that I'd simply put it down to people believing a theist would fear eternal damnation, but rather that a theist would be morally binded not just by their belief in God, but also they would be morally binded by the 'social contract' and also by law. For an atheist, well - two outta three ain't bad, as Meatloaf would say.

    IMO their observations shouldn't be uncomfortable for atheists, but rather they should be more uncomfortable for people who aren't atheist, as the study is an observation of peoples prejudice and bias against atheists, not atheists' bias and prejudice against theists - atheists aren't the people who have a problem, it's people who have the problem with atheists, insofar as they believe them to lack the moral boundaries of theists.


  • Advertisement
  • Registered Users Posts: 26,511 ✭✭✭✭Peregrinus


    IMO their observations shouldn't be uncomfortable for atheists, but rather they should be more uncomfortable for people who aren't atheist, as the study is an observation of peoples prejudice and bias against atheists, not atheists' bias and prejudice against theists - atheists aren't the people who have a problem, it's people who have the problem with atheists, insofar as they believe them to lack the moral boundaries of theists.
    Atheists are people too, Jack! One of the finding of the survey was that the anti-atheist bias it (allegedly) detected was shared by atheists and theists alike.


  • Registered Users Posts: 9,348 ✭✭✭nozzferrahhtoo


    I think in order to truly test bias and prejudice against atheists they would have had to ask questions more along the lines of presenting a moral dilema scenario and asking what would either an atheist or a theist be more likely to do in that scenario, rather than presenting a scenario where a person has already committed the immoral action and then asking participants whether the person is more likely to be atheist or theist.

    I would go further. Often when constructing studies and questionaires and the like to study X, it is best to do as little as possible to mention X as you can. Because there is a kind of "performer bias" in studies where people, when they cop what variable you are testing for, try to give you the positive result they think you want.

    So best would be to construct such a study, with moral dilemas, and then ask the people being studied what would have helped mediate such a situation, what things in a persons life might have helped them positively or negatively in the situations, or made them avoid the moral transgression/problem entirely. No mention to religion (or lack of it) at all.

    SOME of the scenarios should be predicated on, or orbit around, religion or atheists themes too, but not all of them, but the questions about those scenarios should not focus on that aspect directly (or, if possible, at all).

    Even better is in one round of tests leave religion out of it and collate the answers given. Then in another round introduce religious and atheist aspects to the characters and measure how peoples answers differed or drifted from the original ones.

    THEN the wealth of data can be trawled to view mentions of religion, and peoples biases and ideas on how religion would have affected the scenario.
    I'd simply put it down to people believing a theist would fear eternal damnation, but rather that a theist would be morally binded not just by their belief in God, but also they would be morally binded by the 'social contract' and also by law. For an atheist, well - two outta three ain't bad, as Meatloaf would say.

    I loved a recent report on sticking a picture of eyes on the wall in various situations. Turns out that the presence merely of a picture of eyes is enough to motivate people to work harder, with more honesty, and to consider things like social good over personal gain more. Even though the eyes are just a picture and someone knows that, it still affects them.

    The idea of a celestial pair of eyes that can see not only what you do, but what you think, feel and desire and can convict you (as the Christian Nazerene does) of thought crime is one that should certainly have similar effects I suppose. Thankfully some of us do not need fairy tale in order to self-cajole ourselves into being a better person.


  • Registered Users Posts: 23,899 ✭✭✭✭One eyed Jack


    Peregrinus wrote: »
    Atheists are people too, Jack! One of the finding of the survey was that the anti-atheist bias it (allegedly) detected was shared by atheists and theists alike.


    I genuinely hadn't meant to suggest otherwise, but reading back, yeah, I can see how that may have been perceived. Certainly wasn't meant that way! My line of thinking is there's no way to identify a person either as a theist or an atheist without them explicitly saying so, so the idea that a person could be unconsciously biased against a person for something they couldn't even be unconsciously aware of about the person, seems a bit like looking for a problem that just isn't there. It's akin to the same idea as someone like Milo Stewart using the concept of unconscious bias to suggest everyone's a little bit racist, homophobic, transphobic, etc, with no evidence to support their assertion.

    It's not entirely unusual to understand that atheists may be biased against atheists on the basis of other values they associate with their atheism, for example a conservative atheist may be biased against a liberal atheist or vice versa in the same way as someone who identifies as a member of a group may be biased or prejudiced against other members of that group. Atheism+ for example, or Richard Dawkins suggesting that atheists should "come out" in the same way as the LGBT community gained visibility and representation in society - people who weren't LGBT saw that they weren't any different from them, thereby reducing bias and prejudice against them.

    The study does say though that they controlled for these other factors, and they say their hypothesis also held for other conditions such as horoscopes, global warming and vaccines. It says it tweaked the questions and the methodology to account for other factors in the various countries, but this would IMO have influenced how the scientists interpreted the study themselves - in trying to avoid the WEIRD perspective, it appears to me at least that it's still influencing their interpretation of the data.


  • Registered Users Posts: 6,544 ✭✭✭Samaris


    Well, there is an argument that gets trotted out fairly often that the concept of "morality" is specifically religious at base and not having a concept of morality to follow makes atheists de facto immoral and therefore more likely to do immoral things. Of course, once you start judging morality through the lens of any given religion, there will be certain things that atheists may well be more likely to do or allow that are profoundly "immoral" to that religion - gay rights being one possibility. Not to say that atheists cannot be against homosexuality or abortion or any of the other flashpoints between secular and religious living and rule of law, but homosexuality in particular does tend to have a religious line through it in terms of debate. Abortion is a lot more mixed, although definitely has religiously motivated arguments Anti-vax nonsense is quite often a liberal lunacy rather than a religious conservative one, despite the "God wills it" strain of anti-vaxxers. (For ease, I'm mostly taking Christianity here, but same goes for various others.)

    So from that point of view, sure, atheists are less moral by the lights of most mainstream religions. On the other hand, it is complete nonsense to indicate that people are not perfectly capable of controlling themselves to their own standards of decency and morality by their own willpower rather than fear of what comes after death. Rather underestimates human personality and social instincts to suggest otherwise. And specifically in the case of killing people, I hardly know the numbers off the top of my head, but religion has often been used as a justification amongst ordinary people (leaving nations aside a moment as there's too many political slants to take into account as well) for murder - honour killings, "religious mania", etc.


  • Registered Users Posts: 18,430 ✭✭✭✭silverharp


    ^^
    wasn't the basic point of religion in the past to keep stupid people in line which gave that society an evolutionary advantage.

    A belief in gender identity involves a level of faith as there is nothing tangible to prove its existence which, as something divorced from the physical body, is similar to the idea of a soul. - Colette Colfer



  • Advertisement
  • Moderators, Music Moderators Posts: 25,868 Mod ✭✭✭✭Doctor DooM


    I know I should probably add something to the conversation but can I just say how nice it is to see Scofflaw posting.

    Carry on :)


  • Registered Users Posts: 23,283 ✭✭✭✭Scofflaw


    I don't know that I'd agree that it shows us that without thinking about it people were more likely to believe an atheist more capable of immoral acts than a theist. That's the thing I find very unusual in their methodology for testing unconscious bias and prejudice against atheists. I think in order to truly test bias and prejudice against atheists they would have had to ask questions more along the lines of presenting a moral dilema scenario and asking what would either an atheist or a theist be more likely to do in that scenario, rather than presenting a scenario where a person has already committed the immoral action and then asking participants whether the person is more likely to be atheist or theist.

    Unfortunately, what you'd be testing there is something different - you'd be asking people whether they consciously thought an atheist or a believer was more likely to commit such acts.

    As I've already said, the point of the conjunction fallacy is that it only works because people let a believable congruent* narrative trump the rational consideration that it's never possible for A+B to be more likely than A alone.

    Now I come to think about it, I didn't actually explain the conjunction fallacy...it goes like this:

    Given the following two statements, which is more likely:

    1. that Cork will suffer a major flooding episode in the next decade

    2. that Cork will suffer a major flooding episode in the next decade due to the actions of the ESB

    Now, it should be obvious that (2) cannot be more probable than (1) because (2) is a more specific version of (1), and (1) includes (2) as well as other causes. However, (2) presents a congruent or compelling narrative, and many people will choose it as the more probable. They shouldn't, but a believable narrative plays merry hell with people's logic faculties.

    cordially,
    Scofflaw

    * 'congruent' is probably a better word than 'believable' there, since the latter suggests that one studies the statement rationally and decides whether to believe it, whereas the whole point is that if you actually study the statement you'll see that it's a fallacy. What one is looking for is where the unconscious bias is sufficiently strong to take the place of rational examination and decision-making.


  • Registered Users Posts: 26,511 ✭✭✭✭Peregrinus


    Samaris wrote: »
    Well, there is an argument that gets trotted out fairly often that the concept of "morality" is specifically religious at base and not having a concept of morality to follow makes atheists de facto immoral and therefore more likely to do immoral things.
    There is such an argument. It is, of course, b@lls. But, yeah, the prevalence of the argument could contribute to the perceptions that this study observes.
    Samaris wrote: »
    Of course, once you start judging morality through the lens of any given religion, there will be certain things that atheists may well be more likely to do or allow that are profoundly "immoral" to that religion - gay rights being one possibility. Not to say that atheists cannot be against homosexuality or abortion or any of the other flashpoints between secular and religious living and rule of law, but homosexuality in particular does tend to have a religious line through it in terms of debate. Abortion is a lot more mixed, although definitely has religiously motivated arguments Anti-vax nonsense is quite often a liberal lunacy rather than a religious conservative one, despite the "God wills it" strain of anti-vaxxers. (For ease, I'm mostly taking Christianity here, but same goes for various others.)
    To my mind, what’s striking about religiously-influenced ethical systems versus non-religiously-influenced ethical systems is not the differences, but the substantial similarities. Obviously any ethical system starts from some values which are asserted as fundamentally good, without any proof being offered, and then proceeds to build on those, but mostly the edifices built on them are fairly similar. There are a couple of things that can only be judged to be virtuous in a religious ethical system - the moral value of worship is an obvious example - but these are pretty much at the margins.

    Other differences may be more accidental than fundamental. As you say, it’s true for our society that there’s a religious/non-religious fault line in moral views about homosexuality, but I think that’s just the way things have come about. The (largely non-religious) morality of classical Greece was tolerant of certain kinds of homosexual relationship but not of others, so if you contrast that non-religious morality with contemporary non-religious morality you’d have diverging moral views about homosexuality that aren’t attributed to religion. Equally, I don’t think you’d have to look too far to find a non-religious morality that generally condemned homosexuality. (The “socialist morality” of the early Soviet Union, for example, was notably homophobic, as compared with the more relaxed attitudes that prevailed in Tsarist Russia.)

    So, while different moral systems do differ, if we leave aside specifically religious acts like prayer and worship, I’m sceptical that there are many characteristic differences between religious and non-religious moral systems.


  • Moderators, Society & Culture Moderators Posts: 15,754 Mod ✭✭✭✭smacl


    Peregrinus wrote: »
    So, while different moral systems do differ, if we leave aside specifically religious acts like prayer and worship, I’m sceptical that there are many characteristic differences between religious and non-religious moral systems.

    I'm not so sure. If we take morality as being 'principles concerning the distinction between right and wrong or good and bad behaviour' notions such as good demand context, specifically good for other people, good for society or somewhere between the two. If you allow for morality to include social responsibility you have to allow that morality needs to evolve with the needs of society. Looking at Christian morality surrounding sex for example, it was very pragmatic and well suited to the society of its day. Pre-industrial societies with poor medicine and high child mortality rates really want to churn out as many children as the available food source allows for. Homosexuality, contraception and abortion aren't really going to help that, so they're deemed immoral. The problem with religious morality is it tends to stagnate where what was once pragmatic becomes anachronistic dogma as societies needs change over time. In today's society for example, we have too many people, not too few, so the desire to go forth and multiply is actually bad for society and immoral on that basis. Modern notions of morality are more suited to modern society and tend to be more egalitarian and less concerned about the necessities of reproduction than archaic moralities.


  • Registered Users Posts: 26,511 ✭✭✭✭Peregrinus


    Again, I'd be looking for evidence that religiously-based moral systems have a greater tendency to stagnate than non-religiously-based ones. Christian morality didn't have any problem "developing" in relation to matters like military service, usury, slavery; we don't really notice these development because they happened long before our time. We notice sexual morality because our own era is one which has seen significant change in both religious and non-religious moral systems on matters of sexuality, but what really strike us is where there are tensions between different moral systems. But this doesn't necessarily mean that one is stagnant and the other is dynamic; they could both be changing, but in different directions,, or at different speeds, or both. While the Catholic church is holding a line on contraception, for example, Protestants generally embrace it. That's a significant change in (Protestant) Christian morality which has occurred in the last 100 years or so, but what we notice the Catholic intransigence, not the Protestant flexibility. (And even the Catholic position has been massively undermined from within.) And secular attitudes on sexual morality have also changed significantly over the same period; secular moralists are much more accommodating of pre-marital sex and of casual sex than would have been the case a hundred years ago, for example, but much less tolerant of sex with minors, or of sex in the context of unbalanced power relationships.

    At the risk of oversimplifying, don't all moral systems arise out of some interaction between things held as fundamental values, and particular historical circumstances, events and contexts? And since particular historical circumstances, events and contexts are constantly changing, moral systems will be constantly changing with them, but this is going to be true for religious and non-religious systems alike.


  • Moderators, Society & Culture Moderators Posts: 15,754 Mod ✭✭✭✭smacl


    Peregrinus wrote: »
    At the risk of oversimplifying, don't all moral systems arise out of some interaction between things held as fundamental values, and particular historical circumstances, events and contexts? And since particular historical circumstances, events and contexts are constantly changing, moral systems will be constantly changing with them, but this is going to be true for religious and non-religious systems alike.

    To an extent, but religious moral systems tend to be more rigid than non-religious ones. The notion of morality as a set of rules handed down by an omniscient deity for man to follow doesn't really leave much scope for revision by the masses, and it gets left to the senior hierarchy of the day to best interpret the deities intention in the context of their own needs as well as societies. Even within the hierarchy, change is extremely difficult and slow to effect on this basis. As religious morality falls too far behind the needs of society, it gets abandoned by the masses and the religion loses credibility as a result. So for example, while Catholics aren't allowed use contraception, they do. While the Vatican lobbied against gay equality, the people ignored them. As with Protestantism, the religion and its attendant morality might become fractured, or as we see with increasing atheism, abandoned altogether.

    I would suggest that non-religious morality is more flexible than religious morality as it is based more on principles than specific rules. Of course many religious people could see the rigidity of their system a strength rather than a weakness. YMMV.


  • Registered Users Posts: 26,511 ✭✭✭✭Peregrinus


    smacl wrote: »
    To an extent, but religious moral systems tend to be more rigid than non-religious ones. The notion of morality as a set of rules handed down by an omniscient deity for man to follow doesn't really leave much scope for revision by the masses . . .
    But secular moral systems aren't determined by popular vote either, are they?

    As I say, moral systems propose fundamental values and fundamental ways of looking at the world, which you either accept or you don't accept. You either do or don't accept the fundamentals of, say, stoicism. If nobody accepts them, stoicism just withers on the vine. (And, right enough, not many people identify as ethical stoics today.) Just as plenty of religious moral systems have died off.

    In the end, the only moral systems that survive as living, influential systems, are those which are accepted by the masses, and which contine to be accepted over the centuries. The ones that are most likely to sustain that acceptance, I suggest, are likely to be the ones most capable of adapting themselves to new or developing circumstances. By those measures, Christian ethics scores quite well, if only because it has been widely accepted, and widely influential, for a couple of millenia now. Which suggests that it might be a bit more adaptable than the stereotype you are proposing.

    While you describe it as "a set of rules handed down by an omniscient deity for man to follow", and there's at least one sense in which is this is how it presents itself, there are other ways of looking at it. In the Christian view, it's not simply the case that "thou shalt not kill" is a moral imperative because God has said it. It's the other way around; God said it because it's a moral imperative. Which explain how lots of societies recognised it, or something very like it, as a moral imperative, long before they had any contact with Judeo-Christian religion.

    On this view, "thou shalt not kill' is a law in the way that the law of gravity is a law. It doesn't originate as a legislative command; it originates as an observation of, and deduction from, the world. Its expression in the decalogue makes it an authoritative observation and deduction, but it's an observation and deduction that you can make without any authority at all.

    Which means that its no more inherently rigid or immutable than any other observation/deduction that you can make from nature. So the Jude-Christian moral tradition doesn't confine itself to saying "God said this! Now let ye all shut up and do as ye're told, ye blackguards!" On the contrary, the tradition is full of discourse and discussion about questions like, Why did God say this? What does it mean? What exactly is the problem with killing anyway? What are we called to do if somebody wants to kill us? How does this relate to other moral precepts - e.g. can I kill somebody who is going to rape me? Who is going to rape somebody else? Who wants to steal my goods? My land? Who is treating me unjustly?

    And out of all this discourse, a pretty flexible morality emerges - one which can run from absolute pacifism at one extreme to accommodating the death penalty, just war theory, the divine right of kings, medieval notions of chivalry, crusades, etc, etc, etc. And I can think of a number of criticisms of that which would carry more weight than a complaint that it's rigid, immutable, inflexible, incapable of adaptation. Ittoo[/i] capable, if anything.


  • Moderators, Society & Culture Moderators Posts: 15,754 Mod ✭✭✭✭smacl


    Peregrinus wrote: »
    In the Christian view, it's not simply the case that "thou shalt not kill" is a moral imperative because God has said it. It's the other way around; God said it because it's a moral imperative.

    Nonetheless God apparently said it, which is one reason why Christians adhere to it and other similar moral imperatives. I suppose the reason I consider religious morality to have stagnated is that God hasn't said anything much else in recent times. As an atheist, I might look at the last line of your statement above and change it to read 'Man said God said it because it's a moral imperative', yet man hasn't said that God has spoken since, thus religious folk are left trying to apply ancient ideas to modern problems for which they are not a good fit.
    And out of all this discourse, a pretty flexible morality emerges - one which can run from absolute pacifism at one extreme to accommodating the death penalty, just war theory, the divine right of kings, medieval notions of chivalry, crusades, etc, etc, etc. And I can think of a number of criticisms of that which would carry more weight than a complaint that it's rigid, immutable, inflexible, incapable of adaptation. It

    Again, this could be ascribed to a lack of any new definitive guidance from Himself. The freedom you're referring to is surely a result of this vacuum in the worst way possible.


  • Registered Users Posts: 26,511 ✭✭✭✭Peregrinus


    Again, smacl, you're just trotting out simplistic caricatures as if you thought they were an accurate reflection of reality. They're not; they are simplistic caricatures constructed for polemical purposes. They may be closer to the truth for some varieties of religion than for others, but if your case is that religious ethics in general are more rigid than non-religious ethics, then you have to advance arguments that are generally valid.

    I think you're taking the simplistic biblical literalism exhibited by a particular, not very mainsream, Chrisitan tradition, and assuming that it's an accurate representation for all religions in all times. It isn't. Even sticking to Christianity, it's plainly not true that Christians believe that God hasn't spoken since the Bible was produced; one of the central points of debate within Christianity today is the way(s) in which revelation is encountered, but there is no significant Christian tradition which holds that revelation stopped when the last work of the New Testament was written.

    And in your last sentence you seem to glide smoothly from an assertion that the Christian moral tradition is rigid, frozen to an assertion that it provides freedom in the worst way possible. No offence, but this isn't really coherent.

    Given the preconceptions you appear to hold about religion, you would expect religious morality to be rigid and fixed. We observe that, in fact, it's diverse and flexible. If you're committed to evidence-based belief, shouldn't that lead you to critically appraise your preconceptions about religious morality?


  • Registered Users Posts: 9,348 ✭✭✭nozzferrahhtoo


    Peregrinus wrote: »
    By those measures, Christian ethics scores quite well, if only because it has been widely accepted, and widely influential, for a couple of millenia now.

    The problem with a religion morality or ethical system however is many of them, and it is often so with Christian ones, are founded on the opinions of an eternal and unchanging god.

    And that limits the ability of the ethical system to adapt and modify itself in a changing world, and to reflect modernity. They can not retrospectively keep changing what god allegedly said (though some try). So instead they have to find more inventive ways to interpret it to eek out the result they new moral stand point required.

    But, much like retrospectively applying Nostradamus to real world events in order to show it predicted them, the language of texts like the Bible is labile enough to allow such interpretation. Which is likely the source of some of the adaptability you describe.

    But I still see religion adding nothing TO our moral and ethical discourse, and because of the above it can hinder it in many ways (unwillingness to change the teachings and then the unwillingness of the target to accept it) and the adaptability of the vague and labile text is more changing the packing the moral conclusions are delivered in, rather than the underlying product.
    Peregrinus wrote: »
    it's not simply the case that "thou shalt not kill" is a moral imperative because God has said it. It's the other way around; God said it because it's a moral imperative.

    That is one of the interesting examples of labile vagueness to which I refer. Many people have the commandment not as kill but "Thou shalt not murder". And then, of course, what constitutes actual "murder" has many subjective interpretations.

    A lot of the Christian Right for example in the US hold with gun ownership for example. Their preclusion on killing does not include burglars in their house. Nor does it preclude, in the Bible, wiping out entire cultures (keeping the women and virgin children for themselves of course on the way). And the old apocryphal nonsense of "no atheists in foxholes" supposes religiosity therefore on the soldiers who are happily ignoring the commandments and going around offing as many of the enemy as they can.

    So while the commandment appears clear on a first reading, it certainly leaves room for the "adaptability" you imagine in the ethical systems by leaving it strongly open as to exactly what activities the commandment even applies to. It is adaptable because a commandment like that is, essentially, saying nothing at all. So you can merely insert in what you WANT it to mean. A soldier can insert one thing, a US president another, a life long extreme pacifist another.
    Peregrinus wrote: »
    Its expression in the decalogue makes it an authoritative observation and deduction, but it's an observation and deduction that you can make without any authority at all.

    Many people accuse theists of claiming atheists are immoral. And many theists DO.

    But the more "nuanced" theist, debaters like Craig for example, point out that atheists can be moral and have morals......... but without a divine authority they have no valid basis for having any morality at all. They can BE moral, but they can not rationally sit down and defend any moral without an appeal to divine authority.

    So I guess what you write above, if I am parsing it correctly, would put you in conflict with him and many like him?
    Peregrinus wrote: »
    So the Jude-Christian moral tradition doesn't confine itself to saying "God said this! Now let ye all shut up and do as ye're told, ye blackguards!"

    Alas it seems to be the tradition with any theist I have come into conflict with on moral issues, especially the issue of homosexuality. But that could of course be self selecting as the KIND of theist who would do exactly that is also the KIND of theist that would stand up and make noise on those particular types of issue.

    But certainly when, again to use homosexuality as an example, I come into conflict with theists who have a religious concern again something (abortion too for example) they are often unable to rationalize WHY their god might have an issue with it. So they very much do come with the "god says so, so there" approach.

    But they tell me their god is a rational god, so you would think they would at least TRY to co-rationalize with said god and think "Can we discern why god has an issue with this victimless choice of other human beings, and if not is there a possibility WE might have taken our god up wrong on this one?"

    I can not really name theists I have seen do THAT. Except Andrew Sullivan of course, but him BEING gay probably opens up accusations of bias and spin and agenda.
    Peregrinus wrote: »
    And out of all this discourse, a pretty flexible morality emerges

    I fear therefore that it is not that it is flexible. Rather than everyone simply has their own interpretation to fill in the GAPING holes that their text leaves for them to work with. It is not, therefore, that the religious morality in question is flexible. It is that it is essentially non-existent and it is the diversity of human opinion on display, not religious moral flexibility.

    There is a world of difference between "Flexible in the face of input" and "Offering no frame work that in any way hinders input". And I fear many mistake the latter as the former.

    Giving someone an empty box and saying they can put anything they want in it, does not REALLY mean the "box" is particularly flexible.


  • Advertisement
Advertisement